The importance of being rational /:
"The Importance of Being Rational systematically defends a novel reasons-based account of rationality. The book's central thesis is that what it is for one to be rational is to correctly respond to the normative reasons one possesses. Errol Lord defends novel views about what it is to poss...
Gespeichert in:
1. Verfasser: | |
---|---|
Format: | Elektronisch E-Book |
Sprache: | English |
Veröffentlicht: |
Oxford, United Kingdom :
Oxford University Press,
2018.
|
Schlagworte: | |
Online-Zugang: | Volltext |
Zusammenfassung: | "The Importance of Being Rational systematically defends a novel reasons-based account of rationality. The book's central thesis is that what it is for one to be rational is to correctly respond to the normative reasons one possesses. Errol Lord defends novel views about what it is to possess reasons and what it is to correctly respond to reasons. He shows that these views not only help to support the book's main thesis, they also help to resolve several important problems that are independent of rationality. The account of possession provides novel contributions to debates about what determines what we ought to do, and the account of correctly responding to reasons provides novel contributions to debates about causal theories of reacting for reasons. After defending views about possession and correctly responding, Lord shows that the account of rationality can solve two difficult problems about rationality. The first is the New Evil Demon problem. The book argues that the account has the resources to show that internal duplicates necessarily have the same rational status. The second problem concerns the deontic significance of rationality. Recently it has been doubted whether we ought to be rational. The ultimate conclusion of the book is that the requirements of rationality are the requirements that we ultimately ought to comply with. If this is right, then rationality is of fundamental importance to our deliberative lives."-- |
Beschreibung: | 6.4.1 Part I: against the Normative Reasons-First view |
Beschreibung: | 1 online resource (xv, 261 pages) |
Bibliographie: | Includes bibliographical references (pages {243]-253) and index. |
ISBN: | 9780192546746 0192546740 |
Internformat
MARC
LEADER | 00000cam a2200000 i 4500 | ||
---|---|---|---|
001 | ZDB-4-EBA-on1038483164 | ||
003 | OCoLC | ||
005 | 20241004212047.0 | ||
006 | m o d | ||
007 | cr cnu---unuuu | ||
008 | 180602t20182018enk ob 001 0 eng d | ||
040 | |a EBLCP |b eng |e rda |e pn |c EBLCP |d YDX |d UAB |d LGG |d STBDS |d N$T |d OH1 |d CUS |d FIE |d OTZ |d U3W |d CEF |d BRX |d OCLCQ |d UKAHL |d OH# |d OCLCQ |d OCLCO |d OCLCQ |d SFB |d OCLCQ |d OCLCO |d OCLCL |d TMA |d CUS |d OCLCQ |d VLB | ||
019 | |a 1038481693 |a 1038594838 |a 1039054462 |a 1046449161 |a 1049289324 | ||
020 | |a 9780192546746 |q (electronic bk.) | ||
020 | |a 0192546740 |q (electronic bk.) | ||
020 | |z 0198815093 | ||
020 | |z 9780198815099 | ||
020 | |z 9780191852916 | ||
020 | |z 0191852910 | ||
035 | |a (OCoLC)1038483164 |z (OCoLC)1038481693 |z (OCoLC)1038594838 |z (OCoLC)1039054462 |z (OCoLC)1046449161 |z (OCoLC)1049289324 | ||
050 | 4 | |a B833 |b .L67 2018 | |
050 | 4 | |a BC177 | |
072 | 7 | |a PHI |x 010000 |2 bisacsh | |
082 | 7 | |a 128.33 | |
049 | |a MAIN | ||
100 | 1 | |a Lord, Errol, |e author. |0 http://id.loc.gov/authorities/names/n2015026222 | |
245 | 1 | 4 | |a The importance of being rational / |c Errol Lord. |
264 | 1 | |a Oxford, United Kingdom : |b Oxford University Press, |c 2018. | |
264 | 4 | |c ©2018 | |
300 | |a 1 online resource (xv, 261 pages) | ||
336 | |a text |b txt |2 rdacontent | ||
337 | |a computer |b c |2 rdamedia | ||
338 | |a online resource |b cr |2 rdacarrier | ||
588 | 0 | |a Print version record. | |
505 | 0 | |a Cover; The Importance of Being Rational; Copyright; Dedication; Preface; Contents; PART I: Initial Motivations; 1: Introduction: Reasons Responsiveness, the Reasons Program, and Knowledge-First; 1.1 An Ideological Primer; 1.1.1 Rationality, what; 1.1.2 Reasons Responsiveness as a real definition; 1.1.3 Objective normative reasons, what; 1.1.4 Possessed normative reasons, what; 1.1.5 Correctly responding to possessed normative reasons, what; 1.1.6 The requirements of rationality; 1.2 The Reasons Program and Knowledge-First; 1.2.1 The Reasons Program; 1.2.2 Knowledge-first; 1.3 The Plan | |
505 | 8 | |a 2: The Coherent and the Rational2.1 Introduction; 2.2 The Debate as it Currently Stands; 2.3 Broome's Challenge; 2.4 What about Coherence?; 2.4.1 Closure; 2.4.2 Narrowly inconsistent intentions; 2.4.3 Broadly inconsistent intentions; 2.4.4 Means-end incoherence; 2.4.5 Akrasia; 2.5 Practical Condition Failures, High-Order Defeat, and Rational Incoherence; 2.5.1 Practical condition failures; 2.5.2 Higher-order defeat; 2.6 The Myth of the Coherent; 2.7 Back to the Beginning; PART II: Possessing Reasons; Summary of Part I and Introduction to Part II | |
505 | 8 | |a 3: What it is to Possess a Reason: The Epistemic Condition3.1 Introduction; 3.2 A Taxonomy; 3.3 Against Holding Views; 3.4 Against Low Bar Views; 3.5 Against Non-Factive Views; 3.5.1 For (2); 3.5.2 Back to (1); 3.6 Against P TEAR; 3.7 Conclusion; 4: What it is to Possess a Reason: The Practical Condition; 4.1 The Insufficiency of the Epistemic Condition; 4.2 The Counterexamples: A Diagnosis of What's GoingWrong; 4.3 Filling the Gap; 4.3.1 First attempt: missing beliefs(ish); 4.3.2 Second attempt: attitudinal orientation towards the right and good; 4.4 The Practical Condition and Know-How | |
505 | 8 | |a 4.4.1 Inferring desires from knowledge4.4.2 Generalizing; 4.5 Is Possession Composite?; PART III: Correctly Responding to Reasons; Summary of Part II and Introduction to Part III; 5: What it is to Correctly Respond to Reasons; 5.1 Introduction; 5.2 Acting for Motivating Reasons, Believing for Motivating Reasons, and Being Deviant; 5.3 Reacting for Normative Reasons; 5.4 Reacting for Normative Reasons, Essentially Normative Dispositions, and Know-How; 5.4.1 Essentially normative dispositions and deviancy; 5.4.2 Essentially normative dispositions and know-how | |
505 | 8 | |a 5.4.3 Why this is, alas, not enough to get all that we want5.5 Further Upshots; 5.5.1 The relationship between ex post and ex ante rationality; 5.5.2 Speckled hens and the epistemology of perception; 5.5.3 The causal efficacy of the normative; 5.6 Conclusion; 6: Achievements and Intelligibility: For Disjunctivism about Reacting for Reasons; 6.1 Introduction; 6.2 Reacting for Motivating Reasons and Reacting for Normative Reasons; 6.2.1 Reacting for motivating reasons; 6.2.2 Reacting for normative reasons; 6.3 The Univocal View and the Argument from Illusion; 6.4 Against the Univocal View | |
500 | |a 6.4.1 Part I: against the Normative Reasons-First view | ||
520 | |a "The Importance of Being Rational systematically defends a novel reasons-based account of rationality. The book's central thesis is that what it is for one to be rational is to correctly respond to the normative reasons one possesses. Errol Lord defends novel views about what it is to possess reasons and what it is to correctly respond to reasons. He shows that these views not only help to support the book's main thesis, they also help to resolve several important problems that are independent of rationality. The account of possession provides novel contributions to debates about what determines what we ought to do, and the account of correctly responding to reasons provides novel contributions to debates about causal theories of reacting for reasons. After defending views about possession and correctly responding, Lord shows that the account of rationality can solve two difficult problems about rationality. The first is the New Evil Demon problem. The book argues that the account has the resources to show that internal duplicates necessarily have the same rational status. The second problem concerns the deontic significance of rationality. Recently it has been doubted whether we ought to be rational. The ultimate conclusion of the book is that the requirements of rationality are the requirements that we ultimately ought to comply with. If this is right, then rationality is of fundamental importance to our deliberative lives."-- |c Publisher's website | ||
504 | |a Includes bibliographical references (pages {243]-253) and index. | ||
650 | 0 | |a Rationalism. |0 http://id.loc.gov/authorities/subjects/sh85111520 | |
650 | 6 | |a Rationalisme. | |
650 | 7 | |a rationalism (philosophy) |2 aat | |
650 | 7 | |a PHILOSOPHY |x Movements |x Humanism. |2 bisacsh | |
650 | 7 | |a Rationalism |2 fast | |
758 | |i has work: |a The importance of being rational (Text) |1 https://id.oclc.org/worldcat/entity/E39PCG3YXJVw9BpFXdKdfYKkMq |4 https://id.oclc.org/worldcat/ontology/hasWork | ||
776 | 0 | 8 | |i Print version: |a Lord, Errol. |t Importance of being rational. |d Oxford, United Kingdom : Oxford University Press, 2018 |z 9780198815099 |w (OCoLC)1013965812 |
856 | 4 | 0 | |l FWS01 |p ZDB-4-EBA |q FWS_PDA_EBA |u https://search.ebscohost.com/login.aspx?direct=true&scope=site&db=nlebk&AN=1815776 |3 Volltext |
938 | |a Askews and Holts Library Services |b ASKH |n AH37166782 | ||
938 | |a Askews and Holts Library Services |b ASKH |n AH37166781 | ||
938 | |a ProQuest Ebook Central |b EBLB |n EBL5401015 | ||
938 | |a EBSCOhost |b EBSC |n 1815776 | ||
938 | |a Oxford University Press USA |b OUPR |n EDZ0001893520 | ||
938 | |a YBP Library Services |b YANK |n 15468083 | ||
938 | |a YBP Library Services |b YANK |n 15117782 | ||
994 | |a 92 |b GEBAY | ||
912 | |a ZDB-4-EBA | ||
049 | |a DE-863 |
Datensatz im Suchindex
DE-BY-FWS_katkey | ZDB-4-EBA-on1038483164 |
---|---|
_version_ | 1816882460927983616 |
adam_text | |
any_adam_object | |
author | Lord, Errol |
author_GND | http://id.loc.gov/authorities/names/n2015026222 |
author_facet | Lord, Errol |
author_role | aut |
author_sort | Lord, Errol |
author_variant | e l el |
building | Verbundindex |
bvnumber | localFWS |
callnumber-first | B - Philosophy, Psychology, Religion |
callnumber-label | B833 |
callnumber-raw | B833 .L67 2018 BC177 |
callnumber-search | B833 .L67 2018 BC177 |
callnumber-sort | B 3833 L67 42018 |
callnumber-subject | B - Philosophy |
collection | ZDB-4-EBA |
contents | Cover; The Importance of Being Rational; Copyright; Dedication; Preface; Contents; PART I: Initial Motivations; 1: Introduction: Reasons Responsiveness, the Reasons Program, and Knowledge-First; 1.1 An Ideological Primer; 1.1.1 Rationality, what; 1.1.2 Reasons Responsiveness as a real definition; 1.1.3 Objective normative reasons, what; 1.1.4 Possessed normative reasons, what; 1.1.5 Correctly responding to possessed normative reasons, what; 1.1.6 The requirements of rationality; 1.2 The Reasons Program and Knowledge-First; 1.2.1 The Reasons Program; 1.2.2 Knowledge-first; 1.3 The Plan 2: The Coherent and the Rational2.1 Introduction; 2.2 The Debate as it Currently Stands; 2.3 Broome's Challenge; 2.4 What about Coherence?; 2.4.1 Closure; 2.4.2 Narrowly inconsistent intentions; 2.4.3 Broadly inconsistent intentions; 2.4.4 Means-end incoherence; 2.4.5 Akrasia; 2.5 Practical Condition Failures, High-Order Defeat, and Rational Incoherence; 2.5.1 Practical condition failures; 2.5.2 Higher-order defeat; 2.6 The Myth of the Coherent; 2.7 Back to the Beginning; PART II: Possessing Reasons; Summary of Part I and Introduction to Part II 3: What it is to Possess a Reason: The Epistemic Condition3.1 Introduction; 3.2 A Taxonomy; 3.3 Against Holding Views; 3.4 Against Low Bar Views; 3.5 Against Non-Factive Views; 3.5.1 For (2); 3.5.2 Back to (1); 3.6 Against P TEAR; 3.7 Conclusion; 4: What it is to Possess a Reason: The Practical Condition; 4.1 The Insufficiency of the Epistemic Condition; 4.2 The Counterexamples: A Diagnosis of What's GoingWrong; 4.3 Filling the Gap; 4.3.1 First attempt: missing beliefs(ish); 4.3.2 Second attempt: attitudinal orientation towards the right and good; 4.4 The Practical Condition and Know-How 4.4.1 Inferring desires from knowledge4.4.2 Generalizing; 4.5 Is Possession Composite?; PART III: Correctly Responding to Reasons; Summary of Part II and Introduction to Part III; 5: What it is to Correctly Respond to Reasons; 5.1 Introduction; 5.2 Acting for Motivating Reasons, Believing for Motivating Reasons, and Being Deviant; 5.3 Reacting for Normative Reasons; 5.4 Reacting for Normative Reasons, Essentially Normative Dispositions, and Know-How; 5.4.1 Essentially normative dispositions and deviancy; 5.4.2 Essentially normative dispositions and know-how 5.4.3 Why this is, alas, not enough to get all that we want5.5 Further Upshots; 5.5.1 The relationship between ex post and ex ante rationality; 5.5.2 Speckled hens and the epistemology of perception; 5.5.3 The causal efficacy of the normative; 5.6 Conclusion; 6: Achievements and Intelligibility: For Disjunctivism about Reacting for Reasons; 6.1 Introduction; 6.2 Reacting for Motivating Reasons and Reacting for Normative Reasons; 6.2.1 Reacting for motivating reasons; 6.2.2 Reacting for normative reasons; 6.3 The Univocal View and the Argument from Illusion; 6.4 Against the Univocal View |
ctrlnum | (OCoLC)1038483164 |
dewey-full | 128.33 |
dewey-hundreds | 100 - Philosophy & psychology |
dewey-ones | 128 - Humankind |
dewey-raw | 128.33 |
dewey-search | 128.33 |
dewey-sort | 3128.33 |
dewey-tens | 120 - Epistemology, causation, humankind |
discipline | Philosophie |
format | Electronic eBook |
fullrecord | <?xml version="1.0" encoding="UTF-8"?><collection xmlns="http://www.loc.gov/MARC21/slim"><record><leader>07153cam a2200661 i 4500</leader><controlfield tag="001">ZDB-4-EBA-on1038483164</controlfield><controlfield tag="003">OCoLC</controlfield><controlfield tag="005">20241004212047.0</controlfield><controlfield tag="006">m o d </controlfield><controlfield tag="007">cr cnu---unuuu</controlfield><controlfield tag="008">180602t20182018enk ob 001 0 eng d</controlfield><datafield tag="040" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="a">EBLCP</subfield><subfield code="b">eng</subfield><subfield code="e">rda</subfield><subfield code="e">pn</subfield><subfield code="c">EBLCP</subfield><subfield code="d">YDX</subfield><subfield code="d">UAB</subfield><subfield code="d">LGG</subfield><subfield code="d">STBDS</subfield><subfield code="d">N$T</subfield><subfield code="d">OH1</subfield><subfield code="d">CUS</subfield><subfield code="d">FIE</subfield><subfield code="d">OTZ</subfield><subfield code="d">U3W</subfield><subfield code="d">CEF</subfield><subfield code="d">BRX</subfield><subfield code="d">OCLCQ</subfield><subfield code="d">UKAHL</subfield><subfield code="d">OH#</subfield><subfield code="d">OCLCQ</subfield><subfield code="d">OCLCO</subfield><subfield code="d">OCLCQ</subfield><subfield code="d">SFB</subfield><subfield code="d">OCLCQ</subfield><subfield code="d">OCLCO</subfield><subfield code="d">OCLCL</subfield><subfield code="d">TMA</subfield><subfield code="d">CUS</subfield><subfield code="d">OCLCQ</subfield><subfield code="d">VLB</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="019" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="a">1038481693</subfield><subfield code="a">1038594838</subfield><subfield code="a">1039054462</subfield><subfield code="a">1046449161</subfield><subfield code="a">1049289324</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="020" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="a">9780192546746</subfield><subfield code="q">(electronic bk.)</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="020" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="a">0192546740</subfield><subfield code="q">(electronic bk.)</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="020" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="z">0198815093</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="020" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="z">9780198815099</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="020" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="z">9780191852916</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="020" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="z">0191852910</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="035" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="a">(OCoLC)1038483164</subfield><subfield code="z">(OCoLC)1038481693</subfield><subfield code="z">(OCoLC)1038594838</subfield><subfield code="z">(OCoLC)1039054462</subfield><subfield code="z">(OCoLC)1046449161</subfield><subfield code="z">(OCoLC)1049289324</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="050" ind1=" " ind2="4"><subfield code="a">B833</subfield><subfield code="b">.L67 2018</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="050" ind1=" " ind2="4"><subfield code="a">BC177</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="072" ind1=" " ind2="7"><subfield code="a">PHI</subfield><subfield code="x">010000</subfield><subfield code="2">bisacsh</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="082" ind1="7" ind2=" "><subfield code="a">128.33</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="049" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="a">MAIN</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="100" ind1="1" ind2=" "><subfield code="a">Lord, Errol,</subfield><subfield code="e">author.</subfield><subfield code="0">http://id.loc.gov/authorities/names/n2015026222</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="245" ind1="1" ind2="4"><subfield code="a">The importance of being rational /</subfield><subfield code="c">Errol Lord.</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="264" ind1=" " ind2="1"><subfield code="a">Oxford, United Kingdom :</subfield><subfield code="b">Oxford University Press,</subfield><subfield code="c">2018.</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="264" ind1=" " ind2="4"><subfield code="c">©2018</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="300" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="a">1 online resource (xv, 261 pages)</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="336" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="a">text</subfield><subfield code="b">txt</subfield><subfield code="2">rdacontent</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="337" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="a">computer</subfield><subfield code="b">c</subfield><subfield code="2">rdamedia</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="338" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="a">online resource</subfield><subfield code="b">cr</subfield><subfield code="2">rdacarrier</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="588" ind1="0" ind2=" "><subfield code="a">Print version record.</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="505" ind1="0" ind2=" "><subfield code="a">Cover; The Importance of Being Rational; Copyright; Dedication; Preface; Contents; PART I: Initial Motivations; 1: Introduction: Reasons Responsiveness, the Reasons Program, and Knowledge-First; 1.1 An Ideological Primer; 1.1.1 Rationality, what; 1.1.2 Reasons Responsiveness as a real definition; 1.1.3 Objective normative reasons, what; 1.1.4 Possessed normative reasons, what; 1.1.5 Correctly responding to possessed normative reasons, what; 1.1.6 The requirements of rationality; 1.2 The Reasons Program and Knowledge-First; 1.2.1 The Reasons Program; 1.2.2 Knowledge-first; 1.3 The Plan</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="505" ind1="8" ind2=" "><subfield code="a">2: The Coherent and the Rational2.1 Introduction; 2.2 The Debate as it Currently Stands; 2.3 Broome's Challenge; 2.4 What about Coherence?; 2.4.1 Closure; 2.4.2 Narrowly inconsistent intentions; 2.4.3 Broadly inconsistent intentions; 2.4.4 Means-end incoherence; 2.4.5 Akrasia; 2.5 Practical Condition Failures, High-Order Defeat, and Rational Incoherence; 2.5.1 Practical condition failures; 2.5.2 Higher-order defeat; 2.6 The Myth of the Coherent; 2.7 Back to the Beginning; PART II: Possessing Reasons; Summary of Part I and Introduction to Part II</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="505" ind1="8" ind2=" "><subfield code="a">3: What it is to Possess a Reason: The Epistemic Condition3.1 Introduction; 3.2 A Taxonomy; 3.3 Against Holding Views; 3.4 Against Low Bar Views; 3.5 Against Non-Factive Views; 3.5.1 For (2); 3.5.2 Back to (1); 3.6 Against P TEAR; 3.7 Conclusion; 4: What it is to Possess a Reason: The Practical Condition; 4.1 The Insufficiency of the Epistemic Condition; 4.2 The Counterexamples: A Diagnosis of What's GoingWrong; 4.3 Filling the Gap; 4.3.1 First attempt: missing beliefs(ish); 4.3.2 Second attempt: attitudinal orientation towards the right and good; 4.4 The Practical Condition and Know-How</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="505" ind1="8" ind2=" "><subfield code="a">4.4.1 Inferring desires from knowledge4.4.2 Generalizing; 4.5 Is Possession Composite?; PART III: Correctly Responding to Reasons; Summary of Part II and Introduction to Part III; 5: What it is to Correctly Respond to Reasons; 5.1 Introduction; 5.2 Acting for Motivating Reasons, Believing for Motivating Reasons, and Being Deviant; 5.3 Reacting for Normative Reasons; 5.4 Reacting for Normative Reasons, Essentially Normative Dispositions, and Know-How; 5.4.1 Essentially normative dispositions and deviancy; 5.4.2 Essentially normative dispositions and know-how</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="505" ind1="8" ind2=" "><subfield code="a">5.4.3 Why this is, alas, not enough to get all that we want5.5 Further Upshots; 5.5.1 The relationship between ex post and ex ante rationality; 5.5.2 Speckled hens and the epistemology of perception; 5.5.3 The causal efficacy of the normative; 5.6 Conclusion; 6: Achievements and Intelligibility: For Disjunctivism about Reacting for Reasons; 6.1 Introduction; 6.2 Reacting for Motivating Reasons and Reacting for Normative Reasons; 6.2.1 Reacting for motivating reasons; 6.2.2 Reacting for normative reasons; 6.3 The Univocal View and the Argument from Illusion; 6.4 Against the Univocal View</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="500" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="a">6.4.1 Part I: against the Normative Reasons-First view</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="520" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="a">"The Importance of Being Rational systematically defends a novel reasons-based account of rationality. The book's central thesis is that what it is for one to be rational is to correctly respond to the normative reasons one possesses. Errol Lord defends novel views about what it is to possess reasons and what it is to correctly respond to reasons. He shows that these views not only help to support the book's main thesis, they also help to resolve several important problems that are independent of rationality. The account of possession provides novel contributions to debates about what determines what we ought to do, and the account of correctly responding to reasons provides novel contributions to debates about causal theories of reacting for reasons. After defending views about possession and correctly responding, Lord shows that the account of rationality can solve two difficult problems about rationality. The first is the New Evil Demon problem. The book argues that the account has the resources to show that internal duplicates necessarily have the same rational status. The second problem concerns the deontic significance of rationality. Recently it has been doubted whether we ought to be rational. The ultimate conclusion of the book is that the requirements of rationality are the requirements that we ultimately ought to comply with. If this is right, then rationality is of fundamental importance to our deliberative lives."--</subfield><subfield code="c">Publisher's website</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="504" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="a">Includes bibliographical references (pages {243]-253) and index.</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="650" ind1=" " ind2="0"><subfield code="a">Rationalism.</subfield><subfield code="0">http://id.loc.gov/authorities/subjects/sh85111520</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="650" ind1=" " ind2="6"><subfield code="a">Rationalisme.</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="650" ind1=" " ind2="7"><subfield code="a">rationalism (philosophy)</subfield><subfield code="2">aat</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="650" ind1=" " ind2="7"><subfield code="a">PHILOSOPHY</subfield><subfield code="x">Movements</subfield><subfield code="x">Humanism.</subfield><subfield code="2">bisacsh</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="650" ind1=" " ind2="7"><subfield code="a">Rationalism</subfield><subfield code="2">fast</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="758" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="i">has work:</subfield><subfield code="a">The importance of being rational (Text)</subfield><subfield code="1">https://id.oclc.org/worldcat/entity/E39PCG3YXJVw9BpFXdKdfYKkMq</subfield><subfield code="4">https://id.oclc.org/worldcat/ontology/hasWork</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="776" ind1="0" ind2="8"><subfield code="i">Print version:</subfield><subfield code="a">Lord, Errol.</subfield><subfield code="t">Importance of being rational.</subfield><subfield code="d">Oxford, United Kingdom : Oxford University Press, 2018</subfield><subfield code="z">9780198815099</subfield><subfield code="w">(OCoLC)1013965812</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="856" ind1="4" ind2="0"><subfield code="l">FWS01</subfield><subfield code="p">ZDB-4-EBA</subfield><subfield code="q">FWS_PDA_EBA</subfield><subfield code="u">https://search.ebscohost.com/login.aspx?direct=true&scope=site&db=nlebk&AN=1815776</subfield><subfield code="3">Volltext</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="938" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="a">Askews and Holts Library Services</subfield><subfield code="b">ASKH</subfield><subfield code="n">AH37166782</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="938" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="a">Askews and Holts Library Services</subfield><subfield code="b">ASKH</subfield><subfield code="n">AH37166781</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="938" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="a">ProQuest Ebook Central</subfield><subfield code="b">EBLB</subfield><subfield code="n">EBL5401015</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="938" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="a">EBSCOhost</subfield><subfield code="b">EBSC</subfield><subfield code="n">1815776</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="938" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="a">Oxford University Press USA</subfield><subfield code="b">OUPR</subfield><subfield code="n">EDZ0001893520</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="938" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="a">YBP Library Services</subfield><subfield code="b">YANK</subfield><subfield code="n">15468083</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="938" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="a">YBP Library Services</subfield><subfield code="b">YANK</subfield><subfield code="n">15117782</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="994" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="a">92</subfield><subfield code="b">GEBAY</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="912" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="a">ZDB-4-EBA</subfield></datafield><datafield tag="049" ind1=" " ind2=" "><subfield code="a">DE-863</subfield></datafield></record></collection> |
id | ZDB-4-EBA-on1038483164 |
illustrated | Not Illustrated |
indexdate | 2024-11-27T13:28:58Z |
institution | BVB |
isbn | 9780192546746 0192546740 |
language | English |
oclc_num | 1038483164 |
open_access_boolean | |
owner | MAIN DE-863 DE-BY-FWS |
owner_facet | MAIN DE-863 DE-BY-FWS |
physical | 1 online resource (xv, 261 pages) |
psigel | ZDB-4-EBA |
publishDate | 2018 |
publishDateSearch | 2018 |
publishDateSort | 2018 |
publisher | Oxford University Press, |
record_format | marc |
spelling | Lord, Errol, author. http://id.loc.gov/authorities/names/n2015026222 The importance of being rational / Errol Lord. Oxford, United Kingdom : Oxford University Press, 2018. ©2018 1 online resource (xv, 261 pages) text txt rdacontent computer c rdamedia online resource cr rdacarrier Print version record. Cover; The Importance of Being Rational; Copyright; Dedication; Preface; Contents; PART I: Initial Motivations; 1: Introduction: Reasons Responsiveness, the Reasons Program, and Knowledge-First; 1.1 An Ideological Primer; 1.1.1 Rationality, what; 1.1.2 Reasons Responsiveness as a real definition; 1.1.3 Objective normative reasons, what; 1.1.4 Possessed normative reasons, what; 1.1.5 Correctly responding to possessed normative reasons, what; 1.1.6 The requirements of rationality; 1.2 The Reasons Program and Knowledge-First; 1.2.1 The Reasons Program; 1.2.2 Knowledge-first; 1.3 The Plan 2: The Coherent and the Rational2.1 Introduction; 2.2 The Debate as it Currently Stands; 2.3 Broome's Challenge; 2.4 What about Coherence?; 2.4.1 Closure; 2.4.2 Narrowly inconsistent intentions; 2.4.3 Broadly inconsistent intentions; 2.4.4 Means-end incoherence; 2.4.5 Akrasia; 2.5 Practical Condition Failures, High-Order Defeat, and Rational Incoherence; 2.5.1 Practical condition failures; 2.5.2 Higher-order defeat; 2.6 The Myth of the Coherent; 2.7 Back to the Beginning; PART II: Possessing Reasons; Summary of Part I and Introduction to Part II 3: What it is to Possess a Reason: The Epistemic Condition3.1 Introduction; 3.2 A Taxonomy; 3.3 Against Holding Views; 3.4 Against Low Bar Views; 3.5 Against Non-Factive Views; 3.5.1 For (2); 3.5.2 Back to (1); 3.6 Against P TEAR; 3.7 Conclusion; 4: What it is to Possess a Reason: The Practical Condition; 4.1 The Insufficiency of the Epistemic Condition; 4.2 The Counterexamples: A Diagnosis of What's GoingWrong; 4.3 Filling the Gap; 4.3.1 First attempt: missing beliefs(ish); 4.3.2 Second attempt: attitudinal orientation towards the right and good; 4.4 The Practical Condition and Know-How 4.4.1 Inferring desires from knowledge4.4.2 Generalizing; 4.5 Is Possession Composite?; PART III: Correctly Responding to Reasons; Summary of Part II and Introduction to Part III; 5: What it is to Correctly Respond to Reasons; 5.1 Introduction; 5.2 Acting for Motivating Reasons, Believing for Motivating Reasons, and Being Deviant; 5.3 Reacting for Normative Reasons; 5.4 Reacting for Normative Reasons, Essentially Normative Dispositions, and Know-How; 5.4.1 Essentially normative dispositions and deviancy; 5.4.2 Essentially normative dispositions and know-how 5.4.3 Why this is, alas, not enough to get all that we want5.5 Further Upshots; 5.5.1 The relationship between ex post and ex ante rationality; 5.5.2 Speckled hens and the epistemology of perception; 5.5.3 The causal efficacy of the normative; 5.6 Conclusion; 6: Achievements and Intelligibility: For Disjunctivism about Reacting for Reasons; 6.1 Introduction; 6.2 Reacting for Motivating Reasons and Reacting for Normative Reasons; 6.2.1 Reacting for motivating reasons; 6.2.2 Reacting for normative reasons; 6.3 The Univocal View and the Argument from Illusion; 6.4 Against the Univocal View 6.4.1 Part I: against the Normative Reasons-First view "The Importance of Being Rational systematically defends a novel reasons-based account of rationality. The book's central thesis is that what it is for one to be rational is to correctly respond to the normative reasons one possesses. Errol Lord defends novel views about what it is to possess reasons and what it is to correctly respond to reasons. He shows that these views not only help to support the book's main thesis, they also help to resolve several important problems that are independent of rationality. The account of possession provides novel contributions to debates about what determines what we ought to do, and the account of correctly responding to reasons provides novel contributions to debates about causal theories of reacting for reasons. After defending views about possession and correctly responding, Lord shows that the account of rationality can solve two difficult problems about rationality. The first is the New Evil Demon problem. The book argues that the account has the resources to show that internal duplicates necessarily have the same rational status. The second problem concerns the deontic significance of rationality. Recently it has been doubted whether we ought to be rational. The ultimate conclusion of the book is that the requirements of rationality are the requirements that we ultimately ought to comply with. If this is right, then rationality is of fundamental importance to our deliberative lives."-- Publisher's website Includes bibliographical references (pages {243]-253) and index. Rationalism. http://id.loc.gov/authorities/subjects/sh85111520 Rationalisme. rationalism (philosophy) aat PHILOSOPHY Movements Humanism. bisacsh Rationalism fast has work: The importance of being rational (Text) https://id.oclc.org/worldcat/entity/E39PCG3YXJVw9BpFXdKdfYKkMq https://id.oclc.org/worldcat/ontology/hasWork Print version: Lord, Errol. Importance of being rational. Oxford, United Kingdom : Oxford University Press, 2018 9780198815099 (OCoLC)1013965812 FWS01 ZDB-4-EBA FWS_PDA_EBA https://search.ebscohost.com/login.aspx?direct=true&scope=site&db=nlebk&AN=1815776 Volltext |
spellingShingle | Lord, Errol The importance of being rational / Cover; The Importance of Being Rational; Copyright; Dedication; Preface; Contents; PART I: Initial Motivations; 1: Introduction: Reasons Responsiveness, the Reasons Program, and Knowledge-First; 1.1 An Ideological Primer; 1.1.1 Rationality, what; 1.1.2 Reasons Responsiveness as a real definition; 1.1.3 Objective normative reasons, what; 1.1.4 Possessed normative reasons, what; 1.1.5 Correctly responding to possessed normative reasons, what; 1.1.6 The requirements of rationality; 1.2 The Reasons Program and Knowledge-First; 1.2.1 The Reasons Program; 1.2.2 Knowledge-first; 1.3 The Plan 2: The Coherent and the Rational2.1 Introduction; 2.2 The Debate as it Currently Stands; 2.3 Broome's Challenge; 2.4 What about Coherence?; 2.4.1 Closure; 2.4.2 Narrowly inconsistent intentions; 2.4.3 Broadly inconsistent intentions; 2.4.4 Means-end incoherence; 2.4.5 Akrasia; 2.5 Practical Condition Failures, High-Order Defeat, and Rational Incoherence; 2.5.1 Practical condition failures; 2.5.2 Higher-order defeat; 2.6 The Myth of the Coherent; 2.7 Back to the Beginning; PART II: Possessing Reasons; Summary of Part I and Introduction to Part II 3: What it is to Possess a Reason: The Epistemic Condition3.1 Introduction; 3.2 A Taxonomy; 3.3 Against Holding Views; 3.4 Against Low Bar Views; 3.5 Against Non-Factive Views; 3.5.1 For (2); 3.5.2 Back to (1); 3.6 Against P TEAR; 3.7 Conclusion; 4: What it is to Possess a Reason: The Practical Condition; 4.1 The Insufficiency of the Epistemic Condition; 4.2 The Counterexamples: A Diagnosis of What's GoingWrong; 4.3 Filling the Gap; 4.3.1 First attempt: missing beliefs(ish); 4.3.2 Second attempt: attitudinal orientation towards the right and good; 4.4 The Practical Condition and Know-How 4.4.1 Inferring desires from knowledge4.4.2 Generalizing; 4.5 Is Possession Composite?; PART III: Correctly Responding to Reasons; Summary of Part II and Introduction to Part III; 5: What it is to Correctly Respond to Reasons; 5.1 Introduction; 5.2 Acting for Motivating Reasons, Believing for Motivating Reasons, and Being Deviant; 5.3 Reacting for Normative Reasons; 5.4 Reacting for Normative Reasons, Essentially Normative Dispositions, and Know-How; 5.4.1 Essentially normative dispositions and deviancy; 5.4.2 Essentially normative dispositions and know-how 5.4.3 Why this is, alas, not enough to get all that we want5.5 Further Upshots; 5.5.1 The relationship between ex post and ex ante rationality; 5.5.2 Speckled hens and the epistemology of perception; 5.5.3 The causal efficacy of the normative; 5.6 Conclusion; 6: Achievements and Intelligibility: For Disjunctivism about Reacting for Reasons; 6.1 Introduction; 6.2 Reacting for Motivating Reasons and Reacting for Normative Reasons; 6.2.1 Reacting for motivating reasons; 6.2.2 Reacting for normative reasons; 6.3 The Univocal View and the Argument from Illusion; 6.4 Against the Univocal View Rationalism. http://id.loc.gov/authorities/subjects/sh85111520 Rationalisme. rationalism (philosophy) aat PHILOSOPHY Movements Humanism. bisacsh Rationalism fast |
subject_GND | http://id.loc.gov/authorities/subjects/sh85111520 |
title | The importance of being rational / |
title_auth | The importance of being rational / |
title_exact_search | The importance of being rational / |
title_full | The importance of being rational / Errol Lord. |
title_fullStr | The importance of being rational / Errol Lord. |
title_full_unstemmed | The importance of being rational / Errol Lord. |
title_short | The importance of being rational / |
title_sort | importance of being rational |
topic | Rationalism. http://id.loc.gov/authorities/subjects/sh85111520 Rationalisme. rationalism (philosophy) aat PHILOSOPHY Movements Humanism. bisacsh Rationalism fast |
topic_facet | Rationalism. Rationalisme. rationalism (philosophy) PHILOSOPHY Movements Humanism. Rationalism |
url | https://search.ebscohost.com/login.aspx?direct=true&scope=site&db=nlebk&AN=1815776 |
work_keys_str_mv | AT lorderrol theimportanceofbeingrational AT lorderrol importanceofbeingrational |